Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Kant on eugenics and human nature

The 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is perhaps the central figure in modern philosophy. Although like other philosophers—perhaps most famously Plato—the value he places on rationality as an essential capacity of human nature might suggest his endorsement of attempts to shape human nature through eugenic interventions, there is, in fact, much in Kant’s writings to support anti-eugenic thought.

Introducing Kant
Kant is best known for his formal work in both metaphysics and moral philosophy. Kant is less well-known for his work in anthropology, and perhaps even less so for his pioneering work in the science of generation and heredity. Kant’s interest in the sciences in general, and in anthropology in particular, is in part motivated by his conviction that the ultimate goal for philosophic and scientific inquiry concerns human utility and human dignity. Following Francis Bacon’s (1561-1626) scientific method, Kant thinks that the task of modern science is to interrogate nature so that we can gain instrumental control over it. He argues that we are to use our knowledge of and power over nature for achieving the moral betterment of the human species. Given that he thinks mental illness and severe cognitive impairment, for example, present significant barriers for achieving our moral goal, one might expect to find Kant advocating for genetic engineering if it could help in removing such obstacles. While he predates eugenics as we now understand it, Kant, in fact, claims that attempts to determine in advance what sorts of people there should be by way of artificial engineering would be contrary to the ends of nature itself.

Determining what sorts of people there should be
Martin Gunderson (2007) has recently argued that germ-line engineering that can enhance ‘talents or capacities that enable one to pursue morally justifiable goals is permissible’ on Kantian grounds (Gunderson 92). Germ-line engineering modifies germ cells by introducing functional genes into their genomes. This procedure causes all of the original cells in an organism to contain the modified gene, which means that such modifications become hereditary. Gunderson’s idea is that if ‘germ-line engineering could eliminate … mental illness or even ameliorate it, this would be a great boon for humanity’ (Gunderson 91). While it is true that Kant does think that it is morally permissible to use some medical and scientific advances for the (moral) betterment of humanity, there are at least three reasons why he would view germ-line engineering in particular as morally impermissible.

First, Kant’s theory of human nature is by itself adverse to this kind of genetic engineering that attempts to determine in advance what sorts of people there should be. Second, as the philosopher Jürgen Habermas has argued, germ-line engineering involves the treatment of future generations who have not, and indeed cannot, give their consent for this treatment (Habermas 2003). For Kant, this lack of consent is a moral reason not to pursue germ-line engineering. Third, because the genetic changes made to embryos with germ-line engineering are hereditary and the effects on future generations are both unknown and unpredictable, Kant would no doubt side with current researchers who argue that it is ‘dangerous and ethically unacceptable’ (Lanphier 2015). For present purposes, we shall focus on the first argument just noted, namely Kant’s rejection of genetic engineering.

Kant’s most explicit endorsement of anti-eugenic thought comes by way of an objection to a suggestion proposed by Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertius (1698-1759), a forerunner in the study of heredity in biology. Maupertius’ idea was that through selectively breeding people with the desired, so-called nobler qualities with those of similar stock, humankind could eliminate the degenerative, undesired qualities from the human species. Against Maupertius, Kant argues that, while such a program is in itself feasible, it goes against Nature’s own ends. Kant’s claim is that it is precisely through such diversity and ‘the intermingling of the evil with the good’ that Nature develops the human race, leading it ‘nearer to the perfection of [its moral] destiny’ (Kant 2007, 86-7).

Kant on human nature
To better understand Kant’s suggestion that genetic engineering would be contrary to the aims of Nature it will be instructive to briefly consider his theory of human nature. Kant conceives of human nature teleologically. What this means for Kant is that the human being is in some sense designed to serve a purpose or function. One way in which he describes human nature is in terms of what he calls “natural predispositions” or “natural capacities,” the most fundamental of which are the predispositions to rationality and morality (Kant 2007, 417). It is important that these natural predispositions are understood in the sense of potentialities. As Kant puts it, the human being is an animal that has the capacity for rationality, but the development of rationality in individuals as well as the species is contingent upon a variety of circumstances and it can fail to develop in some cases (Kant 2007, 417). For example, a child born with a severe cognitive impairment might be inhibited from fully developing into a rational and moral agent.

Mixing the good with the bad
It might seem odd to claim that Nature mixes the good with the bad in order to promote the development of the human species. After all, if Nature’s aim really is to lead humankind towards moral perfection, it would seem that severe mental illness and/or cognitive disability are precisely the sorts of things that we should want to eradicate where possible. But, on Kant’s view, this is one kind of conflict that drives the (moral) development of the species itself. And it is this idea that leads him to reject genetic engineering, because interfering with Nature that way would effectively remove the very conditions he thinks drive the development and progress of the species in the first place.

One way in which human diversity and the need to overcome all kinds of adversity help our moral development is precisely because these facts of the human condition force us to confront difficult moral questions about how we ought to regard people who are different from and/or less able than others. Raising and appropriately responding to these sorts of conflict, among others, brings us closer to living up to the (Kantian) moral ideal that the rights and dignity of all human beings ought to be protected from individual and state transgressions.

This of course does not mean that Kant prohibits the treatment of mental illness full-stop, but he does think that it means that we need to think more carefully about the sorts of treatments we do employ. Germ-line engineering that attempts to alter Nature and determine in advance what sorts of people there should be is not an approach that would garner the Kantian seal of approval.

-Alan McLuckie

  • Bacon, F. (2000). The New Organon. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Gunderson, M. (2007). “Seeking Perfection: A Kantian Look at Human Genetic Engineering,” in Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 28, 87-102.

  • Habermas, J. (2003). The Future of Human Nature. Trans. W. Rehg, M. Pensky, and H. Beister. Cambridge: Polity Press.

  • Kant, I. (2007). Anthropology, History, and Education. Trans. M. Gregor, P. Guyer, R. Louden, H. Wilson, A. Wood, G. Zöller, and A Zweig. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lanphier, E. et al. (2015). “Don’t Edit the Human Germ Line,” in Nature News. Nature Publishing Group, from http://www.nature.com/news/don-t-edit-the-human-germ-line-1.17111 (accessed May 15, 2015).

  • Maupertius, P. Système de la nature, in Oeuvres, vol. II. (1756). Lyons.

  • Potts, R. Humanity’s Descent: the Consequences of Ecological Instability. (1996). New York: William Morrow and Company, Inc., 1996.Bashford, A., Levine, P. (Eds.).