Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Dehumanization: psychological aspects

When people dehumanize others, they think of them as subhuman creatures or inanimate objects rather than as human beings. European settlers in the New World thought of their African slaves and indigenous Americans as less than human, and more recently Rwandan genocidaires characterized their victims as cockroaches and snakes, and members of the German Nazi party conceived of Jews as dangerous creatures akin to vermin (to give only three of very many historical examples). Even though it is widely accepted that dehumanization plays an important role in genocide, war, and human rights abuses, there has been surprisingly little research into the nature of the phenomenon, its causes, psychological dynamics, and social functions. In particular, there has been practically no work integrating of psychological research with scholarly work on dehumanization by historians, philosophers, and anthropologists. Dehumanization has often played a role in “negative” eugenics—the sterilization or killing of people deemed to be members of genetically inferior groups.

History of dehumanization
The term “dehumanization” was coined in the early 19th century, and has acquired a wide range of meanings since then. These include: treating certain people in degrading ways (for instance, merely as means to an end), referring to them as non-human animals or as inanimate objects, denying that they possess distinctively human characteristics, treating them in degrading ways that cause them to experience themselves as less than human, denying that they have mental states, conceiving of other people as less human than oneself, (7) conceiving of them as inanimate objects, and (8) conceiving of them as subhuman animals.

These meanings are not equivalent, and for the most part do not entail one another. For example, it is possible to refer to people as subhuman animals (by using such language to denigrate them) without conceiving of them as subhuman animals. Although any and all of these senses of “dehumanization” are pertinent to the treatment of supposedly inferior groups by eugenicists, almost all of the psychological research into dehumanization is concerned with (7) and (8), so this article is mainly focused on dehumanization understood in these ways.

There is evidence that people have dehumanized others at least since the beginning of civilization. There are references to enemies and foreigners as subhuman creatures in the literatures of ancient Egypt, Mesopotamia, and China, and it is also present in the cultural practices of indigenous people all over the world.

Dehumanization and psychology
Dehumanization seems to have been first described as a psychological phenomenon by the 17th century Anglican clergyman Morgan Godwyn, who wrote that slaveholders believed that Africans are “Creatures destitute of Souls, to be ranked among Brute Beasts, and treated accordingly”. The Scottish philosopher David Hume also mentioned our tendency to dehumanize enemies in his 1738 Treatise of Human Nature.

Moving on to more recent work, few psychologists investigated dehumanization prior to Jacques-Philippe Leyens in the 1990s. Leyens studied attitudes toward what psychologists call “in-groups” and “out-groups.” A person’s in-group consists of all of the people that he or she includes as “one of us,” and a person’s out-group consists of all the people that she or he regards as “one of them.” Leyens demonstrated that we tend to attribute only “primary” emotions to members of our out-group (primary emotions are very basic emotions such as anger and fear that we also attribute to many non-human animals), and he found that we are more inclined to attribute “secondary” emotions (more cognitively complex, distinctively human emotions) to in-group members. Leyens interpreted these findings as showing that we are disposed to think of outgroup members as “less human” than in-group members. He called this phenomenon infrahumanization to distinguish it from explicit characterizations of other people as nonhuman animals.

Nicholas Haslam extended Leyens’ work in several key respects. Most importantly, he argues that we operate with two distinct conceptions of what it is to be human, each of which corresponds to a distinctive form of dehumanization. Human nature traits are traits that we share with non-human animals and which distinguish both human beings and nonhuman animals from inanimate objects, whereas uniquely human traits are traits that set us apart from other animals. When we deny that others possess human nature traits, we think of them as machines or other inanimate objects, which Haslam calls this mechanistic dehumanization. When we deny that others possess uniquely human traits we think of them as non-human animals rather than as inanimate objects, which Haslam calls this form of dehumanization animalistic dehumanization. Haslam’s work on dehumanization is very influential, and most contemporary psychological work on the topic draws on it.

Violence, moral disengagement, and psychological essentialism
Virtually all researchers agree that dehumanization is intimately bound up with mass violence and human rights abuses. Most hold that this is explained by the fact that dehumanization causes people to become morally disengaged from those whom they abuse. Conceiving of other people as inanimate objects or nonhuman animals makes it morally permissible to treat them in ways that it is impermissible to treat fellow human beings.

There are three broad views on the relationship between dehumanization, moral disengagement, and human rights abuses. On one view, dehumanization has the function of disabling inhibitions against harming, killing, or exploiting others. According to this view, we dehumanize others in order to make it easier for us to harm them. Another view is that dehumanization has the consequence of facilitating harm, but this is not its function (that is, we do not dehumanize others for the purpose of harming them). A third approach is that dehumanization justifies or excuses violence post hoc rather than being a cause of it.

Much of the psychological literature on dehumanization draws on the theory of psychological essentialism. This theory states that people tend to think of living things (including human beings) as divided into kinds (for example, biological species), and think of each of these kinds as having a causal essence. The causal essence of a kind is supposed to be something that only and all members of the kind possess, which makes it the case that they belong to that kind, and which is, in some sense, “inside” them—for example, in their genes or in their blood. According to some researchers, when we dehumanize others we believe that they do not have a human essence or hold that they have a non-human essence. However, there are controversies about how the notion of psychological essentialism should be used in the context of theories of dehumanization. The eugenics movement was explicitly married to a version of essentialism, in which genes played the role of essences. Some groups were regarded essentially (genetically) inferior, and were to be prevented from transmitting their undesirable essence to future generations, and others, who were regarded as essentially (genetically) superior were encouraged to proliferate their desirable essence by producing children. In reality, equating genes with essences is scientifically erroneous.

Conclusion
When we dehumanize other, we conceive of them as subhuman animals or inanimate objects. This way of thinking enables us to treat the dehumanized population in ways that it would be morally impermissible to treat other human beings—for example, killing them, sterilizing them, or otherwise violating their basic human rights. Dehumanization has often played a role in eugenics, by stigmatizing those who are regarded as genetically inferior as less than human. Psychological research into dehumanization began in the latter part of the 20th century, and there is now a robust literature on it by social psychologists. Recently, philosophers have begun to take an interest in the subject, and are beginning to contribute to our understanding of it. The increasing attention being paid to this phenomenon by psychologists and philosophers, after centuries of relative neglect, promises to transform our understanding of it in years to come.

-David Livingstone Smith

  • Bain, Paul G. et al. (eds.), 2013, Humanness and Dehumanization. New York: Psychology Press.

  • French, Shannon E. and Jack, Anthony I., 2014, “Dehumanizing the enemy: the intersection of neuroethics and military ethics.” In Whetham, David, Responsibilies to Protect: Different Perspectives. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Haslam, Nicholas, 2013, ‘What is dehumanization?’ In Bain, Paul, et. al. (eds.) Humanness and Dehumanization. New York: Psychology Press, 34-48.

  • Kelman Harold. C., 1973, “Violence Without Moral Restraint: Reflections on the Dehumanization of Victims and Victimizers”, Journal of Social Issues 29, pp. 25-61.

  • Jack, Anthony I. et al., 2013, “Seeing Human: Distinct and Overlapping Neural Signatures Associated with Two Forms of Dehumanization”, Neuroimage 79, pp. 313-328.

  • LeMoncheck, Linda, 1985, Dehumanizing Women: Treating Persons as Sex Objects. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allenheld.

  • Leyens, Jacques-Philippe, et al, 2000, “The Emotional Side of Prejudice: The Attribution of Secondary Emotions to Ingroups and Outgroups”, Personality and Social Psychology Review 4, pp. 186–197.

  • Mikkola, Maria, 2011, “Dehumanization”, In Brooks, Thom (ed.), New Waves in Ethics. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan, pp. 128-149.

  • Smith, David L., 2011, Less Than Human: Why We Demean, Enslave, and Exterminate Others. New York: St. Martins Press.

  • Smith, David L., 2014, “Dehumanization, Essentialism, and Moral Psychology”, Philosophy Compass 9, pp. 814-824.