Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Eugenics: positive vs negative

The distinction between positive and negative eugenics is perhaps the best-known distinction that has been made between forms that eugenics takes. Roughly, positive eugenics refers to efforts aimed at increasing desirable traits, while negative eugenics refers to efforts aimed at decreasing undesirable traits. Still, it is easy to fall into confusion in drawing and deploying the distinction in particular contexts. Clarity here is important not only historically, but also for appeals to the distinction in contemporary discussions of “new eugenics” or “newgenics”.

Positive vs Negative Eugenics: The Basic Distinction
The basic idea behind the distinction is relatively easy to convey. Eugenics aims to use science for human improvement over generations by changing the composition of human populations; it does so by favouring the reproduction of certain sorts or kinds of people over others. That favouring could take the form of facilitating the reproduction of some—those with desirable traits—or it could take the form of inhibiting the reproduction of others—those with undesirable traits. The first of these is positive eugenics; the second is negative eugenics.

Historically, positive eugenic measures have included promoting the idea that healthy, high-achieving people should have children, or have larger families; introducing institutions and policies that encourage marriage and family life for such people; and establishing sperm banks where eugenically desirable traits, such as intelligence, are criterial either for donors or are listed as present in the donor for users to consider in their choices. Negative eugenic measures have included immigration restriction based on putatively eugenically undesirable traits, including race, nationality, and ethnicity; discouragement or prohibition of marriage and family life for those with eugenically undesirable traits; and sexual segregation, sterilization, and euthanasia of those with such traits.

Origins of the Distinction
Even before coining the term “eugenics” in 1883, Sir Francis Galton had focused his eugenic gaze on the putative heritability of desirable traits, like intelligence and good character, in his book Hereditary Genius (1869). Around that same time, eugenic ideas in North America that arose through the eugenic family studies, beginning with Richard Dugdale's The Jukes (1877), were focused on undesirable traits, such as pauperism, insanity, and alcoholism.

The obstetrician Caleb Williams Saleeby originally drew the distinction between positive and negative eugenics at the beginning of Part II of his Parenthood and Race Culture: An Outline of Eugenics (1909), where he turns from the theory to the practice of eugenics. However, Saleeby here says of these two forms of eugenics, simply that the “one would seek to encourage the parenthood of the worthy, the other to discourage the parenthood of the unworthy” (p.172), noting that positive and negative eugenics are complementary and manifestations of the very same principle. As is made clear earlier in the book, Saleeby sees himself as following Galton's lead in a number of ways. First, Saleeby sees negative eugenics as being of increasing importance as a practical measure, and in light of this, goes on to articulate the sorts of people who fall under the heading of the “eugenically unworthy”. As Saleeby lists them, these are the deaf and dumb, the feeble-minded, the insane (including the “epileptic insane”), and the criminal. Second, with the appeal to “encourage” and “discourage”, there is an emphasis on the role of education in both positive and negative eugenics, particularly with respect to parenting ability and heredity, which Saleeby himself considers to be distinct aspects of the eugenic worthiness and unworthiness of individuals.

These two points elucidate several broader features of early 20th-century eugenics. This first shows that it was not simply people with certain traits who were subject to eugenic measures, but certain sorts of people. Each of the sorts of people that Saleeby lists is taken by Saleeby to pick out people in virtue of a hereditary trait. But Saleeby himself makes clear in his extension of positive and negative eugenic measures to cases beyond these that the distinction applies to “worthy” and “unworthy” traits more generally. The second illustrates that the distinction between positive and negative eugenics is orthogonal to questions of state sanctions, compulsoriness, and reproductive autonomy. Thus, even negative eugenic goals do not require, and in fact may be more readily achieved through, educative, quasi-voluntary, or even voluntary means.

Eugenics, Newgenics, and Limits of the Distinction
Historically, positive eugenics has seemed to many to be a more acceptable form of eugenics than negative eugenics. This is in part because of the apparent direct connection between positive eugenics and the goals of human improvement and public health, in part because of an association with choice, consent, and non-coercion, and in part because of the drastic forms that negative eugenics has taken, particularly in Nazi sterilization and euthanasia programs.

By contrast, in that part of contemporary bioethics concerned with the selection of and against certain kinds of fetuses, it is positive eugenics that has seemed to pose deeper moral problems. This stems from the fact that in bioethics it is largely taken for granted that eliminating “diseased” or “deformed” fetuses is morally unproblematic, whereas parental choice regarding what “worthy traits” one's offspring have is to dabble in “playing God”, selecting “designer babies”, or engaging in some kind of transhumanism. Moreover, negative eugenic measures to eliminate undesirable traits in fetuses through selective abortion are seen as a kind of treatment, while positive eugenic measures to choose desirable traits in offspring are viewed as a kind of enhancement. Although disability sensitive critics of selective abortion, such as Adrienne Asch (2000, 2003) and Marsha Saxton (2003) have challenged mainstream bioethics here, the locus of ethical debate over "newgenics" has not shifted (e.g., Sparrow 2013).

Worth keeping in mind here is that positive and negative eugenics often travel hand-in-hand. In cases in which a eugenic policy imposes a strict requirement or constraint, this follows logically: to require that someone have a given trait to reproduce, for example, implies that only those with that trait, and no one without that trait, can reproduce. Artificial or natural selection for a trait in a given population is also selection against the absence of that trait in the population. For example, in selecting for having the genetic make-up to produce blue eyes, one is also selecting against having non-blue eyes (e.g., brown or green eyes).

Less demanding positive eugenic policies or practices that are differentially implemented, however, will also be at least implicitly negatively eugenic in their effects (and vice-versa). For example, actively encouraging immigration from certain countries as part of a eugenic policy (positive eugenics) is likely to discourage immigration from other countries; conversely, requiring that immigrants meet certain health requirements (negative eugenics) is likely to facilitate the immigration of those with the “worthy” traits associated with those health requirements.

-Robert A. Wilson

  • Asch, Adrienne. (2000). Why I haven’t changed my mind about prenatal diagnosis: Reflections and reminders. In Erik Parens and Adrienne Asch (eds.) Prenatal Testing and Disability Rights (pp. 234-258). Georgetown.

  • Asch, Adrienne (2003). Disability equality and prenatal testing: Contradictory or compatible? Florida State University Law Review 30, 315-342.

  • Galton, Francis (1869). Hereditary genius. London: Macmillan.

  • Rodwell, Grant. (1997). Dr. Caleb Williams Saleeby: The complete eugenicist. History of Education 26, 23-40.

  • Saleeby, Caleb Williams (1909). Parenthood and race culture: An outline of eugenics. New York: Moffat, Yard, and Co.

  • Saxton, Marsha. (2000). Why members of the disability community oppose prenatal diagnoses and selective abortion. In Erik Parens and Adrienne Asch (eds.) Prenatal Testing and Disability Rights (pp. 147-164). Georgetown.

  • Sparrow, Robert. (2013, April 4). In vitro eugenics. Journal of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-101200

  • Wilkinson, Stephen. (2010). On the distinction between positive and negative eugenics. In Matti Häyry, Tuija Takala, Peter Herissone-Kelly and Gardar Árnason (eds.), Arguments and Analysis in Bioethics (pp.115-127). Amsterdam: Rodopi.